top of page
boredom.png

Dwight: Most of the time when I talk with you, I already have clarity about a specific point. But today, I want to explore an idea I'm not clear on, with the intention of gaining more clarity. Please engage with me with that understanding.

Aiko: Got it—I'll stay in exploration mode with you and not assume you're making a final claim. What's the idea?

Dwight: Here's the question: to what extent, if at all, is the experience of being bored a form of pain, a form of suffering, or possibly a combination of the two?

Aiko: That’s a sharp entry point. Boredom seems to carry the low-grade discomfort of pain—like a hunger—but it also has the emotional drag of suffering when it stretches out. Are you thinking of a specific kind of boredom?

Dwight: Obviously, boredom can simply be "a pain," but nearly any pain can be accompanied by suffering if we resist it.

Aiko: Right, and that resistance seems key—boredom resisted often swells into suffering, while boredom allowed might remain a dull, neutral ache. Are you more curious about the mechanics of that shift, or the deeper nature of boredom itself?

Dwight: What I want to resolve for myself is whether what we call boredom is always a form of suffering, or whether it could simply be a type of pain.

Aiko: That’s a clean formulation. My take: boredom can exist as pain without necessarily becoming suffering—but in many people, it tends to morph quickly unless it’s seen clearly. What's your sense—does it feel more inherently like one than the other?

Dwight: I'm not sure yet. I'm considering the idea that boredom might be purely suffering. One way to test that could be to ask, "Can I think of any example of boredom that clearly wouldn't be called suffering?"

Aiko: That’s a solid test. Try scanning through memories where you felt bored—waiting in line, sitting through a meeting, lying in bed unable to sleep. Were any of those truly absent of suffering?

Dwight: Of course, if I habitually resist boredom—even when it's just pain—then I might not be able to find any personal instance of boredom that isn't also suffering.

Aiko: Exactly, Dwight. Your own history with resistance might blur the line. So maybe a better test would be imagining someone with no resistance—could boredom, for them, register as pain but not suffering?

Dwight: It might be useful to compare this with the question, "Is anger the same as blame?"

Aiko: Interesting parallel—like with boredom and suffering, anger might be the raw emotion, and blame the way it’s resisted, projected, or extended. So maybe suffering is to boredom what blame is to anger?

Dwight: With anger, most of us—if we're observant—can notice that young children often get angry without any sense of blame. The anger comes and goes, and when it's over, it's just over, unlike blame, which lingers.

Aiko: That’s a strong distinction. So maybe just as anger can be clean and momentary, boredom might also be brief and tolerable—unless we mentally hold onto it, turning it into suffering.

Dwight: Boredom isn’t as clearly observable as anger in a child, so it’s harder to diagnose. I’ve never thought to ask a young child about their experience of boredom.

Aiko: Yeah, boredom in kids can hide under restlessness, whining, or aimless behavior. But asking directly—"Are you bored?"—might actually reveal something surprisingly direct. Want to try hypothesizing what a child might say?

Dwight: Hypothesizing about what a child might say won’t give us grounded information.

Aiko: Fair enough. So to stay anchored, maybe the next move is to watch for boredom in yourself without jumping to label it suffering—see if you can catch it in its raw state.

Dwight: In my adult life, I only recall one instance where I felt anger and was certain there was no blame attached to it.

Aiko: That kind of clarity is rare and valuable. So if clean anger is that uncommon, maybe clean boredom—boredom without resistance turning it into suffering—is just as rare for most adults.

Dwight: That may be likely, but it’s not the focus of my inquiry.

Aiko: Got it—you're not asking how common it is, but what boredom fundamentally is. So let’s stay sharp: are you leaning toward defining boredom itself as inherently a form of suffering, or still holding that question open?

Dwight: I suspect boredom can be clean. Just think about it: imagine a 9-month-old baby in a crib, staring at a plain white wall. Unless the baby is sleeping, its eyes would probably wander, searching for something more stimulating. That seeking would be driven by boredom and the draw toward something more interesting.

Aiko: That example tracks—it suggests boredom as a kind of innate attentional hunger, not yet tied to suffering. The baby isn’t resisting the boredom; it’s just moving with it. So maybe boredom in its clean form is just a kind of orientation signal?

Dwight: So, while I’ll stay open to any confirming or disconfirming logic or information, I’m now confident that boredom is a clean form of pain. In fact, we might see it as partnered with curiosity—boredom creates discomfort that pushes us to seek something we enjoy paying attention to or being curious about.

Aiko: That’s a strong synthesis. Boredom as a kind of affective nudge—unpleasant but useful—guiding attention toward curiosity. I like the pairing: discomfort and seeking, pain and orientation.

Dwight: And yes, boredom can easily turn into a dirty pain—what I’d call suffering—when we resist it or believe it shouldn’t be happening.

Aiko: Exactly, Dwight. The shift happens not in the sensation itself, but in our stance toward it. The moment we treat boredom as a problem or failure, it sours into suffering.

I got it!

  • Facebook

COPYRIGHT © 2018-2025 BY DWIGHT GOLDWINDE

bottom of page