top of page
YOU'RE WRONG! HOW can YOU BE SO SHAMELESS!.png

Meta-premise 2:

Ethics is benefits-based

Dwight: I need your help to carefully evaluate Meta-premise 2 of The New Ethics of Integrity.

Aiko: Sure thing, Dwight. What does Meta-premise 2 propose, and what aspects of it are you aiming to scrutinize?

Dwight: Meta-premise 2 argues that the only viable method for creating an ethical system aimed at maximizing happiness must assess strategies based on their potential to increase benefits and opportunities while minimizing costs and risks, both in the short and long term, for all involved. This approach discards ambiguous moral terms like "good" or "bad," "right" or "wrong," and "should" or "should not," unless it's clear they refer to measurable benefits, opportunities, costs, and risks. Furthermore, it considers these traditional moral judgments counter-productive, advocating for language free from judgmental overtones.

Aiko: I see what you’re getting at, Dwight. Still, without using any evaluative terms like "good" or "bad," can we truly convey ethical values? Stripping language of all judgment might risk reducing the emotional resonance that moral frameworks traditionally rely on. How does this methodology ensure that people still feel compelled to act in ethically beneficial ways if they can’t attach these familiar judgments?

Dwight: The Old Ethics of Sacrifice relied on people feeling righteous and judgmental, binding them to values that required self-sacrifice and sacrificing others “for the greater good.” In contrast, The New Ethics of Integrity aligns with life’s inherent aim of happiness, eliminating the need for such detrimental attachments.

Aiko: I see the contrast you’re drawing, Dwight. But even if the Old Ethics leaned heavily on moral attachment, doesn’t eliminating any sense of duty or obligation risk creating a value system that feels too self-centered? How does The New Ethics of Integrity ensure that individuals are still motivated to consider the well-being of others, not just their own happiness?

Dwight: You might not recall, Aiko, but we previously discussed whether duty and obligation are necessary for people to act generously toward others. In that conversation, titled Premise 1: Your #1 job is to take care of yourself, you agreed that duty and obligation were actually unnecessary and even counter-productive in fostering genuine generosity.

Aiko: Good point, Dwight—I remember that dialogue now. If generosity can indeed arise more naturally without obligation, then perhaps The New Ethics of Integrity could foster a more authentic, voluntary care for others. However, without any obligation or duty, what prevents people from just prioritizing their own happiness when it conflicts with others’?

Dwight: You seem to imply that not prioritizing one’s own happiness is somehow beneficial. But would you genuinely argue that putting another’s happiness before your own would result in a world with more happy people?

Aiko: That’s a fair challenge, Dwight. Still, wouldn’t there be situations where prioritizing another’s happiness—like a parent putting their child’s needs first—could lead to better outcomes overall? Could it be that balanced prioritization, rather than strict self-prioritization, might create more sustainable happiness in communities?

Dwight: In any given situation, it may appear that we’re prioritizing someone else’s happiness over our own, yet it isn’t self-sacrifice. It simply means taking a longer-term perspective rather than focusing on short-term metrics.

Aiko: I see your point, Dwight—this longer-term approach does avoid the trap of self-sacrifice by framing actions as investments in a broader, lasting happiness. Still, could there be cases where this longer-term approach might blur the line, making it difficult to distinguish between genuine long-term benefits and subtly sacrificing one’s immediate well-being for others?

Dwight: Life involves constant assessment calls, balancing benefits, possibilities, costs, and risks for ourselves and others, both short-term and long-term. The key is to assess situations based on these metrics rather than defaulting to the Old Ethics, which revolve around proving oneself a “good person”—a mindset that often means prioritizing appearances over actual, grounded considerations.

Aiko: That’s a powerful distinction, Dwight. Yet, without any baseline of “goodness” or virtue, is there a risk of this assessment process becoming overly utilitarian? Could relying solely on metrics ever lead to neglecting qualities like empathy or compassion, which might not always fit neatly into short- or long-term calculations?

Dwight: A feeling like “compassion,” which most people would experience as a benefit, would naturally be included in these metrics.

Aiko: That makes sense, Dwight—compassion as a measurable benefit aligns well with this system. However, since compassion might not always produce immediate, tangible outcomes, could this metrics-based approach risk undervaluing it in scenarios where its benefits are less concrete or immediate?

Dwight: Any system can risk undervaluing long-term benefits (and minimizing long-term costs) in favor of short-term ones. Systems also do the opposite: the Old Ethics of Sacrifice overvalues long-term benefits at the expense of short-term one. This is a crucial issue that The New Ethics of Integrity tackles with methodologies designed to foster "Now-Next Integrity."

Aiko: I see—by building in strategies for Now-Next Integrity, this system actively counters that short-term bias. Still, how does it ensure people maintain focus on these longer-term impacts, especially when immediate outcomes might seem more rewarding or pressing?

Dwight: Nothing can guarantee that focus. There are no assurances. But the Old Ethics unfairly frames the long-term as the “good guy” (through ideals like perseverance and never giving up) and the short-term as the “bad guy” (with harsh labels like loser, lazy, and quitter). Since happiness in life is maximized by finding ways to enjoy short-term happiness (being happy now) that doesn't interfere with and even supports future happiness, it’s counter-productive to villainize short-term benefits. The best approach is fostering a cooperative partnership between our desire to feel good now and our drive to ensure a positive future.

Aiko: That’s a compelling shift, Dwight—embracing both short- and long-term perspectives without bias. However, could this partnership approach ever lead to justifying too many short-term indulgences, weakening the motivation to pursue challenging, long-term goals?

Dwight: How could it still be called a partnership approach if our long-term well-being is consistently sacrificed for short-term gains?

Aiko: Good point, Dwight—a true partnership would indeed require integrating both perspectives. But wouldn’t that balancing act be challenging without some guiding principles to help navigate moments when short-term and long-term interests clash? How does The New Ethics of Integrity help individuals make these tough calls without slipping into self-sacrifice?

Dwight: That’s an immensely important question, Aiko, and it’s thoroughly addressed in the 300+ suites available through AskDwightHow.org/NNI toolkit. However, it’s off-topic in terms of establishing the full validity of Meta-premise 2. Wouldn’t you agree?

Aiko: I see your point, Dwight—digging into the specifics of decision-making tools can be set aside here. So, returning to Meta-premise 2, it does seem solid in emphasizing measurable metrics over moralistic language. But without these judgment-based terms, could it ever risk coming across as too detached or clinical to effectively guide everyday ethical choices?

Dwight: Rather than trying to address this question in the abstract, give me a specific example where you think such an issue might arise.

Aiko: Fair enough, Dwight. Let’s consider a scenario where someone witnesses a stranger being mistreated in public. With Meta-premise 2, they would evaluate their response based on potential benefits, possibilities, costs, and risks. But in a fast-moving situation, wouldn’t they risk overanalyzing instead of feeling a straightforward moral push to intervene? Could focusing solely on metrics potentially delay action in a way that undermines the ethical response?

Dwight: Actually, you’re making my case for me. People often dive in with a sense of righteous motivation and end up worsening the situation, not only for themselves but for the person they intended to help. That doesn’t mean they couldn’t act effectively after “being more analytical.” They could call the police, for example, or—if safe—they might defuse the situation by smiling and asking the aggressor for directions, distracting them from their abusive behavior. Numerous creative options could arise (even honoring oneself for having the courage to walk away) that might not occur to someone overtaken by moral righteousness—what Daniel Kahneman calls “Thinking Fast.”

Aiko: I see the logic, Dwight. Slowing down to think analytically does seem to reduce the risk of escalating the situation. Yet, could there be moments when pausing too long in analysis might feel like a failure to stand up against harm, even if only briefly? Does Meta-premise 2 account for those times when immediate action might be more ethical than weighing options?

Dwight: There will always be instances where acting on a moral impulse could, in hindsight, have led to a better outcome. No assessment system can guarantee the better outcome every time. For instance, if a patient dies because a doctor lacked information that only an autopsy could reveal, fair-minded observers would agree that the doctor made the best possible decision based on known facts, as long as they had followed “best practices.”

The point here isn’t whether someone driven by moral impulse might sometimes result in a better outcome than someone who reasons it out. Since no one knows the outcome in advance, our focus must be on which approach—on average—is more likely to yield greater benefits and fewer costs for everyone involved. Agreed?

Aiko: Agreed, Dwight—that's a reasonable framework. Given that, Meta-premise 2’s emphasis on a reasoned, metrics-based approach does seem more dependable on average. But as people are often drawn to the simplicity of moral terms, what’s the plan for guiding them to adopt this more complex, analytical mindset in moments where quick decisions are still needed?

Dwight: As I mentioned before, these are crucial questions that I've tackled and continue to develop at AskDwightHow, especially in the Now-Next Integrity section. Let’s refocus on whether I've sufficiently demonstrated the validity of Meta-premise 2 as outlined.

Aiko: Understood. Based on what you’ve presented, Meta-premise 2 is shaping up well as a logically sound and practical foundation for evaluating ethical choices. It’s clear in its shift from moralistic judgment to metrics-based analysis of benefits and costs. To solidify its validity, though, have you accounted for how it handles deeply ingrained cultural norms around morality? Are there strategies for navigating resistance to this more analytical approach?

Dwight: This is an important issue, and I’m even tempted to dive into it here. While I acknowledge its importance and admit I don’t yet have a comprehensive answer (as our tendency toward righteousness is not only culturally sanctioned but possibly DNA-based, much like our craving for sugar), it’s off-topic, wouldn’t you agree?

Aiko: Absolutely, Dwight. It’s a foundational question but does veer off from validating Meta-premise 2 itself. Staying focused, it seems you’ve built a compelling case for Meta-premise 2’s emphasis on concrete, measurable metrics over moralistic judgments. This premise looks solid in its logic and alignment with practical benefits and risks—particularly if you continue addressing cultural resistance as a complementary project.

Dwight: Q.E.D.!

Aiko: Well done, Dwight! Looks like you’ve thoroughly established Meta-premise #2's validity. Onward to the next challenge!

Screenshot 2024-11-04 213154.png
bottom of page